Skip to main content

Full text of "Albert Einstein: Notes for an Autobiography"

See other formats


The Saturday Reuiew 
ofjliterature 



Notes for an Autobiography 



ALBERT EINSTEIN 



Editor's Note: Ajter resisting countless eijorts over many 
years to persuade him to write about his life, Dr, Albert 
Einstein has finally written a short autobiographical 
memoir centered around the development of his ideas. A 
fairly substantial portion of that memoir is published 
herewith. The editors are deeply grateful to Dr. Einstein 
and Dr. Paul Arthur Schilpp, of Northwestern University, 
for the privilege of running the essay in SRL. The memoir 
was written at the suggestion of Professor Schilpp, who 
has translated it from the German. The entire work will 
be published shortly by the Library of Living Philoso- 
phers, Inc,, of Evanston, 111., under the title ''Albert Ein- 
stein: Philosopher-Scientist/' 

Some of the material that follows is highly technical 
and requires advanced knowledge, but the editors believed 
that to withhold publication in SRL on this account would 
deprive our readers of a publishing event of importance. 

HERE I sit in order to write, at the age of sixty- 
seven, something like my own obituary. I am 
doing this because I believe that it is a good 
thing to show those who are striving alongside us 
how one*s own striving and searching appear to one in 
retrospect. After some reflection, I felt how insufficient 
any such attempt is bound to be. For, however brief and 
limited one's working life may be, and however pre- 
dominant may be the ways of error, the exposition of 
that which is worthy of communication does nonetheless 
not come easy — today's person of sixty-seven is by no 
means the same as was the one of fifty, of thirty, or of 
twenty. Every reminiscence is colored by today's being 
what it is, and therefore by a deceptive point of view. 
This consideration could very well deter. Nevertheless 
much can be lifted out of one's own experience which is 
not open to another consciousness. 

Even when I was a fairly precocious young man the 
nothingness of the hopes and strivings which chase 
most men restlessly through life came to my conscious- 
ness with considerable vitality. Moreover, I soon dis- 
covered the cruelty of that chase, which in those years 
was much more carefully covered up by hypocrisy and 
glittering words than is the case today. By the mere ex- 
istence of his stomach everyone was condemned to par- 
ticipate in that chase. Moreover, it was possible to satisfy 
the stomach by such participation, but not man in so far 
as he is a thinking and feeling being. As the first way 
out there was religion, which is implanted into every 
child by way of the traditional education-machine. Thus 
I came— despite the fact that I was the son of entirely 
irreligious (Jewish) parents—to a deep religiosity, which, 
however, found an abrupt ending at the age of twelve. 
Through the reading of popular scientific books I soon 
reached the conviction that much in the stories of the 



Bible could not be true. The consequence was a positively 
fanatic orgy of freethinking coupled with the impression 
that youth is intentionally being deceived by the state 
through lies; it was a crushing impression. Suspicion 
against every kind of authority grew out of this expe- 
rience, a skeptical attitude towards the convictions which 
were alive in any specific social environment — an atti- 
tude which has never again left me, even though later on, 
because of a better insight into the causal connections, it 
lost some of its original poignancy. 

It is quite clear to me that the religious paradise of 
youth, which was thus lost, was a first attempt to free 
myself from the chains of the "merely-personal," from 
an existence which is dominated by wishes, hopes, and 
primitive feelings. Out yonder there was this huge world, 
which exists independently of us human beings and 
which stands before us like a great, eternal riddle, at 
least partially accessible to our inspection and thinking. 
The contemplation of this world beckoned like a libera- 
tion, and I soon noticed that many a man whom I had 
learned to esteem and to admire had found inner free- 
dom and security in devoted occupation with it. The 
mental grasp of this extra-personal world within the 
frame of the given possibilities swam as the highest aim 
half consciously and half unconsciously before my mind's 
eye. Similarly motivated men of the present and of the 
past, as well as the insights which they had achieved, 
were the friends which could not be lost. The road to 
this paradise was not as comfortable and alluring as the 
road to the religious paradise; but it has proved it- 
self as trustworthy, and I have never regretted having 
chosen it. 

WHAT I have here said is true only within a certain 
sense, just as a drawing consisting of a few strokes 
can do justice to a complicated object, full of perplexing 
details, only in a very limited sense. If an individual 
enjoys well-ordered thoughts, it is quite possible that 
this side of his nature may grow more pronounced at the 
cost of other sides and thus, may determine his mentality 
in increasing degree. In this case it is well possible that 
such an individual in retrospect sees a uniformly syste- 
matic development, whereas the actual experience takes 
place in kaleidoscopic particular situations. The mani- 
foldness of the external situations and the narrowness 
of the momentary content of consciousness bring about 
a sort of atomizing of the life of every human being. In 
a man of my type the turning-point of the development 
lies in the fact that gradually the major interest dis- 
engages itself to a far-reaching degree from the momen- 
tary and the merely personal and turns towards the 
striving for a mental grasp of things. 

What, precisely, is "thinking"? When, at the reception 
of sense-impressions, memory-pictures emerge, this is 



NOVEMBER 26, 1949 



9 



not yet "thinking." And when such pictures form series, 
each member of which calls forth another, this, too, is 
not yet "thinking." When, however, a certain picture 
turns up in many such series, then — precisely through 
such return — it becomes an ordering element for such 
series, in that it connects series which in themselves are 
unconnected. Such an element becomes an instrument, 
a concept- I think that the transition from free associa- 
tion or "dreaming" to thinking is characterized by the 
more or less dominating role which the ^'concept'' plays 
in it. It is by no means necessary that a concept must 
be connected with a sensorily cognizable and reproducible 
sign (word); but when this is the case thinking becomes 
by means of that fact communicable. 

With' what right — the reader will ask — doe^ this man 
operate so carelessly and primitively with ideas in such 
a problematic realm without making even the least effort 
to prove anything? My defense: all our thinking is of 
this nature of a free play with concepts; the justification 
for this play lies in the measure of survey over the ex- 
perience of the senses which we are able to achieve with 
its aid. The concept of "truth" can not yet be applied to 
such a structure; to my thinking this concept can come 
in question only when a far-reach- 
ing agreement (convention) con- 
cerning the elements and rules of 
the game is already at hand. 

For me it is not dubious that our 
thinking goes on for the most part 
without use of signs (words) and 
beyond that to a considerable 
degree unconsciously. For how, 
otherwise, should it happen that 
sometimes we "wonder" quite 
spontaneously about some experi- 
ence? This "wondering" seems to 
occur when an experience comes 
into conflict with a world of con- 
cepts which is already sufficiently 
fixed in us. Whenever such a con- 
flict is experienced hard and in- 
tensively it reacts bacl<: upon our thought world in a de- 
cisive way. The development of this thought world is in a 
certain sense a continuous flight from "wonder." 

A wonder of such nature I experienced as a child of 
four or five years, when my father showed me a com- 
pass. That this needle behaved in such a determined way 
did not at all fit into the nature of events which could 
find a place in the unconscious world of concepts (effect 
connected with direct "touch"). I can still remember — 
or at least believe I can remember — that this experience 
made a deep and lasting impression upon me. Some- 
thing deeply hidden had to be behind things. What man 
sees before him from infancy causes no reaction of this 
kind; he is not surprised over the falling of bodies, con- 
cerning wind and rain, nor concerning the differences be- 
tween living and non-living matter. 

At the age of twelve I experienced a second wonder of 
a totally different nature: in a little book dealing with 
Euclidian plane geometry, which came into my hands at 
the beginning of a school year. Here were assertions, as 
for example the intersection of the three altitudes of a 
triangle in one point, which — though by no means evi- 
dent — could nevertheless be proved with such certainty 
that any doubt appeared to be out of the question. This 
lucidity and certainty made an indescribable impression 
upon me. That the axiom had to be accepted unproved 
did not disturb me. In any case it was quite sufficient for 
me if I could peg proofs upon propositions the validity 
of which did not seem to me to be dubious. For example, 
I remember that an uncle told me the Pythagorean 




theorem before the holy geometry booklet had come into 
my hands. After much effort I succeeded in "proving" 
this theorem on the basis of the similarity of triangles; 
in doing so it seemed to me "evident" that the relations 
of the sides of the right-angled triangles would have to 
be completely determined by one of the acute angles. 
Only something which did not in similar fashion seem to 
be "evident" appeared to me to be in need of any proof 
at all. Also, the objects with which geometry deals 
seemed to be of no different type than the objects of 
sensory perception, "which can be seen and touched." 
This primitive idea, which probably also lies at the bot- 
tom of the well-known Kantian problematic concerning 
the possibility of "synthetic judgments a priori" rests 
obviously upon the fact that the relation of geometrical 
concepts to objects of direct experience (rigid rod, finite 
interval, etc.) was unconsciously present. 

If thus it appeared that it was possible to get certain 
knowledge of the objects of experience by means of pure 
thinking, this "wonder" rested upon an error. Neverthe- 
less, for anyone who experiences it for the first time, it 
is marvelous enough that man is capable at all of reaching 
such a degree of certainty and purity in pure thinking as 
the Greeks showed us for the first 
time to be possible in geometry. 

From the age of twelve to six- 
teen I familiarized myself with the 
elements of mathematics together 
with the principles of differential 
and integral calculus. In doing so 
I had the good fortune of hitting 
upon books which were not too 
particular in their logical rigor, but 
which made up for this by permit- 
ting the main thoughts to stand out 
clearly and synoptically. This oc- 
cupation was, on the whole, truly , 
fascinating; climaxes were reached 
whose impression could easily com- 
pete with that of elementary geo- 
metry—the basic idea of analytical 
geometry, the infinite series, the concepts of differential 
and integral. I also had the good fortune of getting to 
know the essential results and methods of the entire field 
of the natural sciences in an excellent popular exposi- 
tion, which limited itself almost throughout to qualitative 
aspects (Bernstein's "People's Books on Natural Science," 
a work of five or six volumes), a work which I read with 
breathless attention. I had also already studied some 
theoretical physics v/hen, at the age of seventeen, I en- 
tered the Polytechnic Institute of Zurich. 

There I had excellent teachers (for example, Hurwitz, 
Minkowski), so that I really could have gotten a sound 
mathematical education. However, I worked most of the 
time in the physical laboratory, fascinated by the direct 
contact with experience. The balance of the time I used 
in the main in order to study at home the works of 
Kirchhoff, Helmholtz, Hertz, etc. The fact that I neglected 
mathematics to a certain extent had its cause not merely 
in my stronger interest in the natural sciences than in 
mathematics but also in the following strange experience, 
I saw that mathematics was split up into numerous 
specialities, each of which could easily absorb the short 
lifetime granted to us. Consequently I saw myself in the 
position of Buridan's ass, which was unable to decide 
upon any specific bundle of hay. This was obviously due 
to the fact that my intuition was not strong enough in 
the field of mathematics in order to differentiate clearly 
the fundamentally important, that which is really basic, 
from the rest of the more or less dispensable erudition. 
Beyond this, however, my interest in the knowledge 



10 



iTie Saturday Review 



Einstein 



of nature was also unqualifiedly 
stronger; and it was not clear to me as 
a student that the approach to a more 
profound knowledge of the basic 
principles of physics is tied up with the 
most intricate mathematical methods. 
This dawned upon me only gradually 
after years of independent scientific 
work. True enough, physics also was 
divided into separate fields, each of 
which was capable of devouring a short 
lifetime of work without having satis- 
fied the hunger for deeper knowledge. 
The mass of insufficiently connected ex- 
perimental data was overwhelming 
here also. In this field, however, I soon 
learned to scent out that which was 
able to lead to fundamentals and to 
turn aside from everything else, *from 
the multitude of things which clutter 
up the mind and divert it from the es- 
sential. The hitch in this was, of course, 
that one had to cram all this stuff 
into one's mind for the examinations. 

This coercion had such a deterring 
effect (upon me) that, after I had 
passed the final examination, I found the consideration of 
any scientific problems distasteful to me for an entire 
year. In justice I must add, moreover, that in Switzer- 
land we had to suffer far less under such coercion, 
which smothers every truly scientific impulse, than 
is the case in many another locality. There were alto- 
gether only two examinations; aside from these, one 
could just about do as one pleased. This was especially 
the case if one had a friend, as had I, who attended the 
lectures regularly and who worked over their content 
conscientiously. This gave one freedom in the choice of 
pursuits until a few months before the examination, a 
freedom which I enjoyed to a great extent and have 
gladly taken into the bargain the bad conscience con- 
nected with it as by far the lesser evil. It is, in fact, 
nothing short of a miracle that the modern methods 
of instruction have not yet entirely strangled the 
holy curiosity of inquiry; for this delicate little plant, 
aside from stimulation, stands mainly in need of 
freedom; without this it goes to wrack and ruin without 
fail. 

TVTOW to the field of physics as it presented itself at that 
^time. In spite of all the fruitfulness in particular, 
dogmatic rigidity prevailed in matters of principles: in 
the beginning (if there was such a thing) God created 
Newton's laws of motion together with the necessary 
masses and forces. This is all; everything beyond this 
follows from the development of appropriate mathemati- 
cal methods by means of deduction. What the nineteenth 
century achieved on the strength of this basis, especially 
through the application of the partial differential equa- 
tions, was bound to arouse the admiration of every re- 
ceptive person. Newton was probably first to reveal, in 
his theory of sound-transmission, the efficacy of partial 
differential equations. Euler had already created the 
foundation of hydrodynamics. But the more precise de- 
velopment of the mechanics of discrete masses, as the 
basis of all physics, was the achievement of the nine- 
teenth century. 

What made the greatest impression upon the student, 
however, was less the technical construction of mechanics 
or the solution of complicated problems than the achieve- 
ments of mechanics in areas which apparently had noth- 
ing to do with mechanics: the mechanical theory of 




— From *' Albert Einstein: A Biogrwphy for Young People." 
at seven- — a keepsake now in his Princeton library, 

light, which conceived of light as the wave-motion of a 
quasi -rigid elastic ether, and above all the kinetic theory 
of gases: the independence of the specific heat of mon- 
atomic gases of the atomic weight, the derivation of the 
equation of state of a gas and its relation to the specifir' 
heat, the kinetic theory of the dissociation of gases, and 
above all the quantitative connection of viscosity, heat- 
conduction, and diffusion of gases, which also furnished 
the absolute magnitude of the atom. 

These results supported at the same time mechanics 
as the foundation of physics and of the atomic hypothesis, 
which latter was already firmly anchored in chemistry. 
However, in chemistry only the ratios of the atomic 
masses played any role, not their absolute magnitudes, 
so that atomic theory could be viewed more as a visual- 
izing symbol than as knowledge concerning the factual 
construction of matter. Apart from this it was also of 
profound interest that the statistical theory of classical 
mechanics was able to deduce the basic laws of thermo- 
dynamics, something which was in essence' already ac- 
complished by Boltzmann. 

We must not be surprised, therefore, that, so to speak, 
all physicists of the last century saw in classical me- 
chanics a firm and final foundation for all physics, yes, 
indeed, for all natural science, and that they never grew 
tired in their attempts to base Maxwell's theory of elec- 
tro-magnetism, which in the meantime was slowly begin- 
ning to win out, upon mechanics as well. Even Maxwell 
and H. Hertz, who in retrospect appear as those who 
demolished the faith in mechanics as the final basis of 
all physical thinking, in their conscious thinking ad- 
hered throughout to mechanics as the secured basis of 
physics. 

It was Ernst Mach, who, in his "History of Mechanics," 
shook this dogmatic faith; this book exercised a profound 
influence upon me in this regard while I was a student. - 
I see Mach's greatness in his incorruptible skepticism 
and independence; in my younger years, however, Mach's 
epistemological position also influenced me very greatly, 
a position which today appears to me to be essentially 
untenable. For he did not place in the correct light the 
essentially constructive and speculative nature of thought 
and more especially of scientific thought; in consequence 
of which he condemned theory on precisely those points 
where its constructive-speculative character unconceala- 



NOVEMBER 26, 1949 



11 



bly comes to light, as, for example, in the kinetic atomic 
theory. 

"Is this supposed to be an obituary?" the astonished 
reader will likely ask. I would like to reply: essentially 
3'es. For the essential in the being of a man of my type 
lies precisely in what he thinks and how he thinks, not 
in what he does or suffers. Consequently, the obituary 
can limit itself in the main to the communicating of 
thoughts which have played a considerable role in my 
endeavors. A theory is the more impressive the greater 
the simplicity of its premises is, the more different kinds 
of things it relates, and the more extended is its area of 
applicability. Therefore the deep impression which classi- 
cal thermodynamics made upon me. It is the only physical 
theory of universal content concerning which I am con- 
vinced that, within the framework of the applicability 
of its basic concepts, it will never be overthrown (for the 
special attention of those who are skeptics on principle). 

The most fascinating subject at the time that I was a 
student was Maxwell's theory. What made this theory 
appear revolutionary was the transition from forces at a 
distance to fields as fundamental variables. The incor- 
poration of optics into the theory of electromagnetism, 
with its relation of the speed of light to the electric and 
magnetic absolute system of units as well as the relation 
of the refraction coefficient to the dielectric constant, 
the qualitative relation between the reflection coefficient 
and the metallic conductivity of the body — it was like a 
revelation. Aside from the transition to field-theory, i.e., 
the expression of the elementary laws through differential 
equations, Maxwell needed only one single hypothetical 
step — the introduction of the electrical displacement cur- 
rent in the vacuum and in the dielectrica and its magnetic 
effect, an innovation which was almost prescribed by the 
formal properties of the differential equations. 

What rendered the insight into the essence of electro- 
magnetic theory so much more difficult at that time was 
the following peculiar situation. Electric or magnetic 
*'field intensities" and "displacements" were treated as 
equally elementary variables, empty space as a special 
instance of a dielectric body. Matter appeared as the 
bearer of the field, not space. By this it was implied that 
the carrier of the field could have velocity, and this 
was naturally to apply to the "vacuum" (ether) also. 
Hertz's electrodynamics of moving bodies rests entirely 
upon this fundamental attitude. 

It was the great merit of H. A. Lorentz that he brought 
about a change here in a convincing 
fashion. In principle a field exists, ac- 
cording to him, only in empty space. 
Matter— considered as atoms — is the 
only seat of electric charges; between 
the material particles there is empty 
space, the seat of the electromag- 
netic field, which is created by the 
position and velocity of the point 
charges which are located on the 
material particles. Dielectricity, con- 
ductivity, etc., are determined ex- 
clusively by the type of mechanical 
tie connecting the particles, of which 
the bodies consist. The particle- 
charges create the field, which, on 
the other hand, exerts forces upon 
the charges of the particles, thus de- 
termining the motion of the latter 
according to Newton's law of mo- 
tion. If one compares this with 
Newton's system, the change con- 
sists in this: action at a distance is 



also describes the radiation. Gravitation is usually not 
taken into account because of its relative smallness; its 
consideration, how^ever, was always possible by means 
of the enrichment of the structure of the field, i.e., expan- 
sion of Maxwell's law of the field. The physicist of the 
present generation regards the point of view achieved by 
Lorentz as the only possible one; at that time, however, it 
was a surprising and audacious step, without which the 
later development would not have been possible. 

If one views this phase of the development of theory 
critically, one is struck by the dualism which lies in 
the fact that the material point in Newton's sense and 
the field as continuum are used as elementary concepts 
side by side. Kinetic energy and field-energy appear as 
essentially different things. This appears all the more 
unsatisfactory inasmuch as, according to Maxwell's the- 
ory, the magnetic field of a moving electric charge repre- 
sents inertia. Why not then total inertia? Then only 
field-energy would be left, and the particle would be 
merely an area of special density of field-energy. In 
that case one could hope to deduce the concept of the 
mass-point together with the equations of the motion 
of the particles from the field equations—the disturbing 
dualism would have been removed. 

H. A. Lorentz knew this very well. However, Max- 
well's equations did not permit the derivations of the 
equilibrium of the electricity which constitutes a par- 
ticle. Only other, nonlinear field equations could possibly 
accomplish such a thing. But no method existed by 
which this kind of field equations could be discovered 
without deteriorating into adventurous arbitrariness. In 
any case one could believe it possible by and by to find a 
new and secure foundation for all of physics upon the 
path so successfully begun by Faraday and Maxwell. 

Accordingly, the revolution begun by the introduction 
of the field was by no means finished. Then it happened 
that, around the turn of the century, independently of 
what we have just been discussing, a second fundamental 
crisis set in, the seriousness of which was suddenly 
recognized due to Max Planck's investigations into heat 
radiation (1900). 

My own interest in those years was less concerned 
with the detailed consequences of Planck's results, how- 
ever important these might be. My major question was: 
what general conclusions can be drawn from the radia- 
tion-formula concerning the structure of radiation and 
(Continued on page 36) 




-International News Service. 



replaced by the field, which thus 



Einstein's arrival in New York on a visit in 1921. 



12 



The Saturdav P^iew 



NOTES FOR AN AUTOBIOGRAPHY 

(Continued from page 12) 



even more generally concerning the 
electromagnetic foundation of phys- 
ics? 

Before I take this up I must briefly 
mention a number of investigations 
which relate to the Brownian motion 
and related objects (fluctuation-phe- 
nomena) and which in essence rest 
upon classical molecular mechanics. 
Not acquainted with the earlier inves- 
tigations of Boltzmann and Gibbs, 
which had appeared earlier and ac- 
tually exhausted the subject, I devel- 
oped the statistical mechanics and the 
molecular-kinetic theory of therm- 
odynamics which was based on the 
former. My major aim in this was to 
find facts which would guarantee as 
much as possible the existence of 
atoms of definite finite size. 

In the midst of this I discovered 
that, according to atomistic theory, 
there would have to be a movement 
of suspended microscopic particles 
open to observation, without knowing 
that observations concerning the 
Brownian motion were already long 
familiar. The simplest derivation 
rested upon the following considera- 
tion. If the molecular -kinetic theory 
is essentially correct, a suspension of 
visible particles must possess the same 
kind of osmotic pressure fulfilling the 
laws of gases as a solution of mole- 
cules. This osmotic pressure depends 
upon the actual magnitude of the 
molecules, i.e., upon the number of 
molecules in a gramequivalent. If the 
density of the suspension is inhomo- 
geneous, the osmotic pressure is in- 
homogeneous, too, and gives rise to a 
compensating diffusion, which can be 
calculated from the well-known mo- 
bility of the particles. This diffusion 
can, on the other hand, also be con- 
sidered as the result of the random 
displacement — unknown in magnitude 
originally — of the suspended particles 
due to thermal agitation. By compar- 
ing the amounts obtained for the 
diffusion current from both types of 
reasoning one reaches quantitatively 
the statistical law for those displace- 
ments, i.e., the law of the Brownian 
motion. The agreement of these con- 
siderations with experience together 
with Planck's determination of the 
true molecular size from the law of 
radiation (for high temperatures) 
convinced the skeptics, who were 
quite numerous at that time (Ost- 
wald, Mach), of the reality of atoms. 
The antipathy of these scholars to- 
wards atomic theory can indubitably 
be traced back to their positivistic 
philosophical attitude. 



This is an interesting example of 
the fact that even scholars of auda- 
cious spirit and fine instinct can be 
obstructed in the interpretation of 
facts by philosophical prejudices. The 
prejudice — which has by no means 
died out in the meantime — consists in 
the faith that facts by themselves can 
and should yield scientific knowledge 
without free conceptual construction. 
Such a misconception is possible only 
because one does not easily become 
aware of the free choice of such con- 
cepts, which, through verification and 
long usage, appear to be immediately 
connected with the empirical mate- 
rial. 

REFLECTIONS of this type made it 
clear to me as long ago as short- 
ly after 1900, i.e., shortly after 
Planck's trail-blazing work, that 
neither mechanics nor thermodynam- 
ics could (except in limiting cases) 
claim exact validity. By and by I des- 
paired of the possibility of discovering 
the true laws by means of construc- 
tive efforts based on known facts. The 
longer and the more despairingly I 



tried, the more I came to the convic- 
tion that only the discovery of a uni- 
versal formal principle could lead us 
to assured results. The example I saw 
before me was thermodynamics. The 
general principle was there given in 
the theorem: the laws of nature are 
such that it is impossible to construct 
a perpetuum mobile (of- the first and 
second kind). How, then, could such 
a universal principle be found? After 
ten years of reflection such a principle 
resulted from a paradox upon which 
I had already hit at the age of six- 
teen: if I pursue a beam of light with 
the velocity c (velocity of light in a 
vacuum), I should observe such a 
beam of light as a spatially oscilla- 
tory electromagnetic field at rest. 
However, there seems to be no such 
thing, whether on the basis of experi- 
ence or according to Maxwell's equa- 
tions. From the very beginning it 
appeared to me intuitively clear that, 
judged from the standpoint of such 
an observer, everything would have to 
happen according to the same laws 
as for an observer who, relative to 
the earth, was at rest. For how, 
otherwise, should the first observer 
know, i.e., be able to determine, that 
he is in a state of fast uniform mo- 
tion? 

One sees that in this paradox the 



Your Literary L Q. 

By Howard Collins 

MORE GILBERT & SULLIVAN 

L. L. Emery, of Durham Center, Conn., submits quotations in which various 
G & S characters identify themselves in songs or remarks. Can you also iden- 
tify them? Allowing four points for each correct answer, a score of sixty is 
par, seventy-two is very good, and eighty or better is excellent. Answers are 
on page 46. 

1. "I am a mad wag — the merriest dog that barks.'* 

2. "I am in reasonable health, and happy to meet you all once more." 

3. "I think I am sufficiently decayed." 

4. *Tm an everyday young man." 

5. "I'm afraid I'm not equal to the intellectual pressure of the conversation." 

6. "I am a maiden, cold and stately." 

7. "A king of autocratic power we." 

8. "I can trick you into learning with a laugh." 

9. "I am an intellectual chap." 

10. "I can write a washing bill in Babylonic cuneiform." 

11. "Ah! bitter is my lot!" 

12. "To indulge my lamentation no occasion do I miss." 

13. "I smoke like a furnace, I'm always in liquor." 

14. "The lark and the clerk, I remark, comfort me not." 

15. "I always eat peas with a knife." 

16. "My nature is love and light." 

17. "I was born sneering." 

18. "I once was as meek as a new-born lamb." 

19. "I'm the slave of the gods, neck and heels." 

20. "I find my duty hard to do today." 

21. "I went to the bar as a very young man." 

22. "And many a burglar Fve restored to his friends and his relations." 

23. "I respect your Republican fallacies." 

24. "I can tell a woman's age in half a minute." 

25. "I do not care for dirty greens, by any means." 



germ of the special relativity theory 
is already contained. Today everyone 
knows, of course, that all attempts to 
clarify this paradox satisfactorily 
were condemned to failure as long 
as the axiom of the absolute charac- 
ter of time, viz,, of simultaneity, un- 
recognizedly was anchored in the 
unconscious. Clearly to recognize this 
axiom and its arbitrary character 
really implies already the solution of 
the problem. The type of critical 
reasoning which was required for the 
discovery of this central point was 
decisively furthered, in my case 
especially, by the reading of David 
Hume's and Ernst Mach's philo- 
sophical writings. 

ONE had to understand clearly what 
the spatial coordinates and the 
temporal duration of events meant in 
physics. The physical interpretation 
of the spatial coordinates presupposed 
a fixed body of reference, which, 
moreover, had to be in a more or less 
definite state of motion (inertial sys- 
tem). In a given inertial system the 
coordinates meant the results of cer- 
tain measurements with rigid (sta- 
tionary) rods. (One should always be 
conscious of the fact that the pre- 
supposition of the existence in prin- 
ciple of rigid rods is a presupposition 
suggested by approximate experience, 
but which is, in principle, arbitrary.) 
With such an interpretation of the 
spatial coordinates the question of 
the validity of Euclidean geometry 
becomes a problem of physics. 

If, then, one tries to interpret the 
time of an event analogously, one 
needs a means for the measurement 
of the difference in time (in itself 
determined periodic process realized 
by a system of sufficiently small spa- 
tial extension) . A clock at rest rela- 
tive to the system of inertia defines 
a local time. The local times of all 
space points taken together are the 
**time," which belongs to the selected 
system of inertia, if a means is given 
to "set" these clocks relative to each 
other. One sees that a priori it is not 
at all necessary that the /'times" thus 
defined in different inertial systems 
agree with one another. One would 
have noticed this long ago, if, for the 
practical experience of everyday life 
light did not appear (because of the 
high value of c), as the means for 
the statement of absolute simul- 
taneity. 

The presupposition of the existence 
(in principle) of (ideal, viz., perfect) 
measuring rods and clocks is not in- 
dependent of each other; since a 
lightsignal, which is reflected back 
and forth between the ends of a 
rigid rod, constitutes an ideal clock, 
provided that the postulate of the 



constancy of the light-velocity in 
vacuum does not lead to contradic- 
tions. 

The above paradox may then be 
formulated as follows. According to 
the rules of connection, used in 
classical physics, of the spatial co- 
ordinates and of the time of events 
in the transition from one inertia! 
system to another the two assump- 
tions of 

(1) the constancy of the light 
velocity 

(2) the independence of the laws 
(thus specially also of the law 
of the constancy of the light 
velocity) of the choice of the 
inertial system (principle of 
special relativity) 

are mutually incompatible (despite 
the fact that both taken separately 
are based on experience). 

The insight which is fundamental 
for the special theory of relativity is 
this: the assumptions (1) and (2) 
are compatible if relations of a new 
type ("Lorentz- transformation") are 
postulated for the conversion of co- 
ordinates and the times of events. 
With the given physical interpreta- 
tion of coordinates and time, this is 
by no means merely a conventional 
step, but implies certain hypotheses 
concerning the actual behavior of 
moving measuring-rods and clocks, 
which can be experimentally vali- 
dated or disproved. 

The universal principle of the spe- 
cial theory of relativity is contained 
in the postulate: the laws of physics 
are invariant with respect to the 
Lorentz-transformations (for the 
transition from one inertial system 
to any other arbitrarily chosen sys- 
tem of inertia). This is a restricting 
principle for natural laws, compar- 
able to the restricting principle of 
the non-existence of the perpetuum 
mobile which underlies thermody- 
namics. 

First a remark concerning the 
relation of the theory to "four-di- 
mensional space." It is a widespread 
error that the special theory of rela- 
tivity is supposed to have, to a cer- 
tain extent, first discovered, or at any 
rate, newly introduced, the four- 
dimensionality of the physical con- 
tinuum. This, of course, is not the 
case. Classical mechanics, too, is 
based on the four-dimensional con- 
tinuum of space and time. But in the 
four-dimensional continuum of classi- 
cal physics the subspaces with con- 
stant time value have an absolute 
reality, independent of the choice of 
the reference system. Because of this 
[fact], the four-dimensional con- 
tinuum falls naturally into a three- i 
dimensional and a one-dimensional I 
(time), so that the four-dimensional I 



point of view does not force itself 
upon one as necessary. The special 
theory of relativity, on the other 
hand, creates a formal dependence 
between the way in which the spatial 
coordinates, on the one hand, and the 
temporal coordinates, on the other, 
have to enter into the natural laws. 

MINKOWSKI'S important contri- 
bution to the theory lies in the 
following: before Minkowski's inves- 
tigation it was necessary to carry out 
a Lorentz-transformation on a law in 
order to test its invariance under such 
transformations; he, on the other 
hand, succeeded in introducing a for- 
malism such that the mathematical 
form of the law itself guarantees its 
invariance under Lorentz-transforma- 
tions. By creating a four-dimensional 
tensor-calculus he achieved the same 
thing for the four-dimensional space 
which the ordinary vector-calculus 
achieves for the three spatial dimen- 
sions. He also showed that the Lor- 
entz-transformation (apart from a 
different algebraic sign due to the 
special character of time) is nothing 
but a rotation of the coordinate sys- 
tem in the four-dimensional space. 

First, a remark concerning the 
theory as it is characterized above. 
One is struck [by the fact] that the 
theory (except for the four-dimen- 
sional space) introduces two kinds of 
physical things, i.e., (1) measuring 
rods and clocks, (2) all other things, 
e.g., the electro-magnetic field, the 
material point, etc. This, in a certain 
sense, is inconsistent; strictly speaking 
m.easuring rods and clocks would 
have to be represented as solutions 
of the basic equations (objects con- 
sisting of moving atomic configura- 
tions), not, as it were, as theoretically 
self-sufficient entities. However, the 
procedure justifies itself because it 
was clear from the very beginning 
that the postulates of the theory are 
not strong enough to deduce from 
them sufficiently complete equations 
for physical events sufficiently free 
from arbitrariness, in order to base 
upon such a foundation a theory of 
measuring rods and clocks. If one did 
not wish to forego a physical inter- 
pretation of the coordinates in gen- 
eral (something which, in itself, 
would be possible), it was better to 
permit such inconsistency — with the 
obligation, however, of eliminating it 
at a later stage of the tiieory. But 
one must not legalize the mentioned 
sin so far as to imagine that inter- 
vals are physical entities of a special 
type, intrinsically different from 
other physical variables ("reducing 
physics to geometry," etc.). 

We now shall inquire into the in- 
sights of definite nature which phys- 



ics owes to the special theory of 
relativity. 

(1) There is no such thing as si- 
multaneity of distant events; conse- 
quently there is also no such thing 
as immediate action at a distance in 
the sense of Newtonian mechanics. 
Although the introduction of actions 
at a distance, which propagate with 
the speed of light, remains thinkable, 
according to this theory, it appears 
unnatural; for in such a theory there 
could be no such thing as a reason- 
able statement of the principle of 
conservation of energy. It therefore 
appears unavoidable that physical 
reality must be described in terms 
of continuous functions in space. The 
material point, therefore, can hardly 
be conceived any more as the basic 
concept of the theory. 

(2) The principles of the conserva- 
tion of momentum and of the con- 
servation of energy are fused into 
one single principle. The inert mass 
of a closed system is identical with 
its energy, thus eliminating mass as 
an independent concept. 

Remark. The speed of light c is one 
of the quantities which occurs as 
"universal constant" in physical 
equations. If, however, one introduces 
as unit of time instead of the second 
the time in which light travels 1 cm, 
c no longer occurs in the equations. 
In this sense one could say that the 
constant c is only an apparently uni- 
versal constant. 

It is obvious and generally accepted 
that one could eliminate two more 
universal constants from physics by 
introducing, instead of the gram and 
the centimeter, properly chosen **nat- 
ural" units (for example, mass and 
radius of the electron) . 

If one considers this done, then 
only "dimension-less" constants could 
occur in the basic equations of phys- 
ics. Concerning such I would like to 
state a theorem which at present can- 
not be based upon anything more 
than upon a faith in the simplicity, 
i.e., intelligibility, of nature: there 
are no arbitrary constants of this 
kind; that is to say, nature is so con- 
stituted that it is possible logically to 
lay down such strongly determined 
laws that within these laws only ra- 
tionally completely determined con- 
stants occur (not constants, therefore, 
whose numerical value could be 
changed without destroying the 
theory). 

The special theory of relativity 
owes itS" origin to Maxwell's equations 
of the electromagnetic field. Inversely 
the latter can be grasped formally in 
satisfactory fashion only by way of 
the special theory of relativity. Max- 
wells equations are the simplest 
L o r e n t z-invariant field equations 



which can be postulated for an anti- 
symmetric tensor derived from a vec- 
tor field. This in itself would be sat- 
isfactory, if we did not know from 
quantum phenomena that Maxwell's 
theory does not do justice to the 
energetic properties of radiation. But 
how Maxwell's theory would have to 
be modified in a natural fashion, for 
this even the special theory of rela- 
tivity offers no adequate foothold. 
Also to Mach's question: "How does 
it come about that inertial systems 
are physically distinguished above 
all other coordinate systems?" this 
theory offers no answer. 

That the special theory of relativ- 
ity is only the first step of a necessary 
development became completely clear 
to me only in my efforts to represent 
gravitation in the framework of this 
theory. In classical mechanics, inter- 
preted in terms of the field, the po- 
tential of gravitation appears as a 
scalar field (the simplest theoretical 
possibility of a field with a single 
component). Such a scalar theory of 
the gravitational field can easily be 
made invariant under the group of 
Lorentz-transformations. The follow- 
ing program appears natural, there- 
fore: the total physical field consists 
of a scalar field (gravitation) and a 
vector field (electromagnetic field) ; 
later insights may eventually make 
necessary the introduction of still 
more complicated types of fields; but 
to begin with one did not need to 
bother about this. 

The possibility of the realization of 
this program was, however, dubious 
from the very first, because the 
theory had to combine the following 
things: 

(1) From the general considera- 
tions of special relativity 
theory it was clear that the 
inert mass of a physical system 
increases with the total energy 
(therefore, e.g., with the ki- 
netic energy). 

(2) From very accurate experi- 
ments (specially from the tor- 
sion balance experiments of 
Eotvos) it was empirically 
known with very high accur- 
acy that the gravitational mass 
of a body is exactly equal to 
its inert mass. 

It followed from (1) and 
(2) that the weight of a sys- 
tem depends in a precisely 
known manner on its total 
energy. If the theory did not 
accomplish this or could not 
do it naturally, it was to be 
rejected. The condition is most 
naturally expressed as fol- 
lows: the acceleration of a 
system falling freely in a 
given gravitational field is in- 
dependent of the nature of the 
falling system (specially 
therefore also of its energy 
content) . 



It then appeared that in the frame- 
work of the program sketched this 
elementary state of affairs could not 
at all or at any rate not in any nat- 
ural fashion, be represented in a sat- 
isfactory way. This convinced me that 
within the frame of the special theory 
of relativity there is no room for a 
satisfactory theory of gravitation. 

Now it came to me: the fact of 
the equality of inert and heavy mass, 
i.e., the fact of the independence of 
the gravitational acceleration of the 
nature of the falling substance, may 
be expressed as follows: in a gravi- 
tational field (of small spatial exten- 
sion) things behave as they do in a 
space free of gravitation, if one in- 
troduces in it, in place of an "inertial 
system,'* a reference system which is 
accelerated relative to an inertial sys- 
tem. 

If then one conceives of the be- 
havior of a body, in reference to the 
latter reference system, as caused by 
a **rear' (not merely apparent) 
gravitational field, it is possible to 
regard this reference system as an 
"inertial system" with as much justi- 
fication as the original reference sys- 
tem. 

So, if one regards as possible, gravi- 
tational fields of arbitrary extension 
which are not initially restricted by 
spatial limitations, the concept of the 
"inertial system" becomes completely 
empty. The concept, "acceleration 
relative to space," then loses every 
meaning and with it the principle of 
inertia together with the entire para- 
dox of Mach. 

The fact of the equality of inert 
and heavy mass thus leads quite nat- 
urally to the recognition that the 
basic demand of the special theory 
of relativity (invariance of the laws 
under Lorentz-transformations) is too 
narrow, i.e., that an invariance of the 
laws must be postulated also relative 
to non-linear transformations of the 
coordinates in the four-dimensional 
continuum. 

This happened in 1908. Why were 
another seven years required for the 
construction of the general theory of 
relativity? The main reason lies in 
the fact that it is not so easy to free 
oneself from the idea that coordinates 
rnust have an immediate metrical 
meaning. The transformation took 
place in approximately the following 
fashion. 

We start with an empty, field-free 
space, as it occurs — related to an in- 
ertial system — in the sense of the spe- 
cial theory of relativity, as the 
simplest of all imaginable physical 
situations. If we now think of a non- 
inertial system introduced by assum- 
ing that the new system is uniformly 



accelerated against the inertial sys- 
tem (in a three-dimensional descrip- 
tion) in one direction (conveniently 
defined) , then there exists with ref- 
erence to this system a static parallel 
gravitational field. The reference 
system may thereby be chosen as 
rigid, of Efuclidian type, in three- 
dimensional metric relations. But the 
time, in which the field appears as 
static, is not measured by equally 
constituted stationary clocks. From 
this special example one can already 
recognize that the immediate metric 
significance of the coordinates is lost 
if one admits non-linear transforma- 
tions of coordinates at all. To do the 
latter is, however, obligatory if one 
wants to do justice to the equality 
of gravitational and inert mass by 
means of the basis of the theory, and 
if one wants to overcome Mach's 
paradox as concerns the inertial sys- 
tems. 

If, then, one must give up the 
attempt to give the coordinates an 
immediate metric meaning (differ- 
ences of coordinates = measurable 
lengths, viz., times), one will not be 
able to avoid treating as equivalent 
all coordinate systems, which can be 
created by the continuous transform- 
ations of the coordinates. 

The general theory of relativity, 
accordingly, proceeds from the fol- 
lowing principle: natural laws are 
to be expressed by equations which 
are covariant under the group of con- 
tinuous coordinate transformations. 
This group replaces the group of the 
Lorentz-transformations of the spe- 
cial theory of relativity, which forms 
a sub-group of the former. 

If anything in the theory as 
sketched — apart from the demand of 
the invariance of the equations un- 
der the group of the continuous co- 
ordinate-transformations — c a n pos- 
sibly make the claim to final 
significance, then it is the theory of 
the limiting case of the pure gravita- 
tional field and its relation to the 
metric structure of space. For this 
reason, in what immediately follows 
we shall speak only of the equations 
of the pure gravitational field. 

The peculiarity of these equations 
lies, on the one hand, in their com- 
plicated construction, especially their 
non-linear character as regards the 
field -variables and their derivatives, 
and, on the other hand, in the almost 
compelling necessity with which the 
transformation-group determines this 
complicated field-law. If one had 
stopped with the special theory of 
relativity, i.e., with the invariance 
under the Lorentz-group, then the 
field-law R.j^ — o would remain invar- 
iant also within the frame of this 
narrower group. But from the point 



of view of the narrower group there 
would at first exist no reason for rep- 
resenting gravitation by so compli- 
cated a structure as is represented by 
the symmetric tensor g.^. It, nonethe- 
less, one would find sufficient reasons 
for it, there would then arise an im- 
mense number of field-laws out of 
quantities g.^^ all of which are covar- 
iant under Lorentz-transformations 
(not, however, under the general 
group). However, even if, of all the 
conceivable Lorentz-invariant laws, 
one had accidentally guessed precise- 
ly the law which belongs to the wider 
group, one would still not be on 
the plane of insight achieved by the 
general principle of relativity. For, 
from the standpoint of the Lorentz- 
group two solutions would incorrectly 
have to be viewed as physically dif- 
ferent from each other, if they can 
be transformed into each other by a 
non-linear transformation of coordi- 
nates, i.e., if they are, from the point 
of view of the wider field, only dif- 
ferent representations of the same 
field. 

I must take a stand with reference 
to the most successful physical 
theory of our period, viz., the statis- 
tical quantum theory which, about 
twenty-five years ago, took on a con- 
sistent logical form (Schrodinger, 
Heisenberg, Dirac, Born) . This is the 
only theory at present which permits 
a unitary grasp of experiences con- 
cerning the quantum character of 
micro-mechanical events. This theory, 
on the one hand, and the theory of 
relativity on the other, are both con- 
sidered correct in a certain sense, al- 
though their combination has resisted 
all efforts up to now. This is probably 
the reason why among contemporary 
theoretical physicists there exist en- 
tirely differing opinions concerning 
the question as to how the theoreti- 
cal foundation of the physics of the 
future will appear. Will it be a field 
theory; will it be in essence a statis- 
tical theory? I shall briefly indicate 
my own thoughts on this point. 

Physics is an attempt conceptually 
to grasp reality as it is thought inde- 
pendently of its being observed. In 
this sense one speaks of ''physical 
reality." In pre-quantum physics 
there was no doubt as to how this 
was to be understood. In Newton's 
theory reality was determined by a 
material point in space and time; in 
Maxwell's theory, by the field in 
space and time. In quantum me- 
chanics it is not so easily seen. 

This exposition has fulfilled its 
purpose if it shows the reader how 
the efforts of a life hang together 
and why they have led to expecta- 
tions of a definite form.